• NEW! LOWEST RATES EVER -- SUPPORT THE SHOW AND ENJOY THE VERY BEST PREMIUM PARACAST EXPERIENCE! Welcome to The Paracast+, eight years young! For a low subscription fee, you can download the ad-free version of The Paracast and the exclusive, member-only, After The Paracast bonus podcast, featuring color commentary, exclusive interviews, the continuation of interviews that began on the main episode of The Paracast. We also offer lifetime memberships! Flash! Take advantage of our lowest rates ever! Act now! It's easier than ever to susbcribe! You can sign up right here!

    Subscribe to The Paracast Newsletter!

Consciousness and the Paranormal

Free episodes:

Status
Not open for further replies.
Online journal: Frontiers in Psychology

Consciousness Research

Research Topic:What can neuroscience learn from contemplative practices?

Topic Editors:
Zoran Josipovic, New York University, USA
Bernard J. Baars

"A recent wave of brain research has advanced our understanding of the neural mechanisms of conscious states, contents and functions. A host of questions remain to be explored, as shown by lively debates between models of higher vs. lower-order aspects of consciousness, as well as global vs. local models. (Baars
2007; Block, 2009; Dennett and Cohen, 2011; Lau and Rosenthal, 2011).

Over some twenty-five centuries the contemplative traditions have also developed explicit descriptions and taxonomies of the mind, to interpret experiences that are often reported in contemplative practices (Radhakrishnan & Moore, 1967; Rinbochay & Naper, 1981). These traditional descriptions sometimes converge on current scientific debates, such as the question of conceptual vs. non-conceptual consciousness; reflexivity or “self-knowing” associated with consciousness; the sense of self and consciousness; and aspects of consciousness that are said to continue during sleep. These real or claimed aspects of consciousness have not been fully integrated into scientific models so far.

This Research Topic in Consciousness Research aims to provide a forum for theoretical proposals, new empirical findings, integrative literature reviews, and methodological improvements inspired by meditation-based models. We are open to a broad array of topics, including but not limited to: replicable findings from a variety of systematic mental practices; changes in brain functioning and organization that can be attributed to such practices; their effects on adaptation and neural plasticity; measurable effects on cognition, affect and the sensory systems; effects on self-referential processes, the default network, mirror neurons, and other observable brain events.

We invite contributions that address the question of causal attribution. Many published studies are correlational in nature, because of the inherent difficulty of conducting longitudinal experiments based on a major lifestyle decision, such as the decision to commit to a mental practice over a period of years. We also welcome rigorous clinical and case studies, developmental studies over the lifespan, integrative syntheses and significant opinion articles. Articles that lack a clear experimental basis in neuroscience or psychology will be at a disadvantage; in particular, speculative opinion pieces not grounded in solid science are likely to be rejected. If you are interested in contributing, please contact the editors with your idea before uploading an abstract, to determine if your topic is is appropriate for this issue."

Consciousness Research | Research Topics

The open-source journal provided at this site is right up the alley of this thread. Here is a list of articles available with a click:

Consciousness Research
 
Another article from that journal, this one apropos of what has seemed to me to be the problem of Tononi's in-the-head approach to information and consciousness. The article does not refer to Tononi; it critiques an article attempting a wholly in-the-head reading of the O'Regan and Noe study of sensorimotor capacities we looked at earlier.

The worldly constituents of perceptual presence
Ezequiel A. Di Paolo1,2,3*
  • 1Ikerbasque, Basque Science Foundation, Bilbao, Spain
  • 2Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science, University of the Basque Country, San Sebastian, Spain
  • 3Centre for Computational Neuroscience and Robotics, University of Sussex, Brighton, UK
A commentary on
A predictive processing theory of sensorimotor contingencies: explaining the puzzle of perceptual presence and its absence in synesthesia

Seth, A. K. (2014). Cogn. Neurosci. doi: 10.1080/17588928.2013.877880. [Epub ahead of print].

In a thought-provoking article, Seth (2014) has elaborated a combined sensorimotor and predictive coding approach to perception. His proposal links perceptual presence with the counterfactual richness of predictive models in the brain, an appealing move, which is not without problems. Here I briefly state my main conceptual concern with the idea. I believe Seth can take this worry into account by shifting the emphasis from the brain to the worldly constituents of perceptual presence.

There are two broad ways of interpreting O'Regan and Noë's (2001) claim that perception depends on the mastery of the laws of sensorimotor contingencies (SMCs). They can be broadly depicted as conceiving mastery as in-the-head or not-just-in-the-head.

In-the-head notions of mastery can be sufficiently pinned down to states in an agent's functional architecture. Whether these are instantiated inside a skull or not, pace the label, doesn't matter; the resulting notion is internalist and representational. Not-just-in-the-head interpreters (e.g., Hutto and Myin, 2013) make appeals to non-representational forms of know-how to account for mastery. . . .
http://journal.frontiersin.org/Journal/10.3389
/fpsyg.2014.00450/full
 
Fuller explication of what is involved in sensorimotor contingencies:

Front. Psychol., 27 May 2013 | doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00285
A dynamical systems account of sensorimotor contingencies
Thomas Buhrmann1*, Ezequiel Alejandro Di Paolo1,2,3 and Xabier Barandiaran1,4
  • 1IAS-Research Centre for Life, Mind, and Society, UPV/EHU, University of the Basque Country, San Sebastian, Spain
  • 2Ikerbasque, Basque Foundation for Science, Bilbao, Spain
  • 3Centre for Computational Neuroscience and Robotics, University of Sussex, Brighton, UK
  • 4Department of Philosophy, UPV/EHU, University of the Basque Country, San Sebastian, Spain
"According to the sensorimotor approach, perception is a form of embodied know-how, constituted by lawful regularities in the sensorimotor flow or in sensorimotor contingencies (SMCs) in an active and situated agent. Despite the attention that this approach has attracted, there have been few attempts to define its core concepts formally. In this paper, we examine the idea of SMCs and argue that its use involves notions that need to be distinguished. We introduce four distinct kinds of SMCs, which we define operationally. These are the notions of sensorimotor environment (open-loop motor-induced sensory variations), sensorimotor habitat (closed-loop sensorimotor trajectories), sensorimotor coordination (reliable sensorimotor patterns playing a functional role), and sensorimotor strategy (normative organization of sensorimotor coordinations). We make use of a minimal dynamical model of visually guided categorization to test the explanatory value of the different kinds of SMCs. Finally, we discuss the impact of our definitions on the conceptual development and empirical as well as model-based testing of the claims of the sensorimotor approach.

Introduction
The sensorimotor approach to perception has generated much interest and debate within cognitive science over the last decade. Bringing together insights from various disciplines such as theories of active perception, dynamical systems, ecological psychology, enactivism, phenomenology, cybernetics, and neuroscience, this approach is identified with an influential paper by O’Regan and Noë (2001). In it and in subsequent work, the authors and colleagues have made strong claims about the sensorimotor basis of perceptual experience, namely that both its content and form (what is perceived and how) are constituted by a know-how of sensorimotor regularities or sensorimotor contingencies (SMCs). This perspective rejects the traditional assumption that perception is fully constituted by computations in the brain. Instead, it sees the perceiver as an active agent engaging with the world and perception as intimately linked to skillful action.

In working out the fine-grained details of this idea, different understandings of the sensorimotor proposal have emerged. In general, they vary in how the dependencies are established between both the actual and potential sensorimotor structures that are available to the active agent (and determined by the agent’s situation, bodily skills, and history), and the quality and content of perception. The connection between subpersonal sensorimotor regularities and the personal experience they constitute is made by an appeal to linkage phrases such as “mastery of the laws of SMCs,” “knowledge of SMCs,” or “sensorimotor skill.” For example, O’Regan and Noë argue that in order for a person to be perceptually aware, he must not only have acquired mastery of SMCs, but also integrate the current exercise of this mastery with processes of reasoning and action guidance (O’Regan and Noë, 2001, p. 944). Much of how the approach should be interpreted hinges on how such linkage terms are understood and ultimately operationalized.

The details of this passage between the subpersonal and personal levels have been the object of much debate (Hutto, 2005; Clark, 2006; Roberts, 2009). It is unclear whether the sensorimotor approach should be understood as a radical departure from traditional computational functionalism or as an enrichment of it. The debates about how this contentious linkage terminology is best interpreted will probably continue, but in this paper we want to draw attention to an important aspect that seems to have been overlooked in these discussions and in the primary literature: the notion of SMCs itself.

An examination of this notion is a step prior to resolving the central issues in ongoing debates. Far from being a straightforward idea, in this paper we argue that the concept needs a clear definition and admits several refinements. We identify four distinct notions of SMCs: sensorimotor environment, sensorimotor habitat, sensorimotor coordination, and sensorimotor strategies. We define these concepts operationally, thus filling what we see as a gap in sensorimotor theory. The four sensorimotor structures are described using dynamical systems terminology although we also show that they can be investigated by a variety of methods. We do not claim that other useful operational definitions are not possible, but we think our definitions cover most of the usages we have identified as intended explicitly or implicitly in the sensorimotor approach. Then we evaluate the usefulness of these concepts by applying them to the analysis of a new minimal cognition model of active categorical perception (following work by Beer and others, e.g., Beer, 2003). This achieves the double purpose of testing the operational character of the proposed ideas and of gaining further insight into their relation. Finally, we discuss the theoretical, empirical, and modeling impact of these four kinds of SMCs. . . ."

Frontiers | A Dynamical Systems Account of Sensorimotor Contingencies | Cognition
 
Another informative article from the Frontiers site, this one concerning the current state of interdisciplinary research into human language capacities . . .

Front. Psychol., 07 May 2014 | doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00401
The mystery of language evolution
Marc D. Hauser1*, Charles Yang2, Robert C. Berwick3, Ian Tattersall4,
newprofile_default_profileimage_new.jpg
Michael J. Ryan5, Jeffrey Watumull6, Noam Chomsky7 and
newprofile_default_profileimage_new.jpg
Richard C. Lewontin8

Abstract: "Understanding the evolution of language requires evidence regarding origins and processes that led to change. In the last 40 years, there has been an explosion of research on this problem as well as a sense that considerable progress has been made. We argue instead that the richness of ideas is accompanied by a poverty of evidence, with essentially no explanation of how and why our linguistic computations and representations evolved. We show that, to date, (1) studies of nonhuman animals provide virtually no relevant parallels to human linguistic communication, and none to the underlying biological capacity; (2) the fossil and archaeological evidence does not inform our understanding of the computations and representations of our earliest ancestors, leaving details of origins and selective pressure unresolved; (3) our understanding of the genetics of language is so impoverished that there is little hope of connecting genes to linguistic processes any time soon; (4) all modeling attempts have made unfounded assumptions, and have provided no empirical tests, thus leaving any insights into language's origins unverifiable. Based on the current state of evidence, we submit that the most fundamental questions about the origins and evolution of our linguistic capacity remain as mysterious as ever, with considerable uncertainty about the discovery of either relevant or conclusive evidence that can adjudicate among the many open hypotheses. We conclude by presenting some suggestions about possible paths forward."


Extracts:

"In summary, the paleontological evidence is silent with respect to the capacity for both the internal computations and representations of language and its externalization in linguistic expression and communication. As we note in our final section, it is conceivable that methodological advances will enable a more fine-grained understanding of internal neurobiological structure from details of skull structure, but we are nowhere near such discoveries at present. Archaeological evidence, in contrast, points to the emergence of a language of thought in early Homo sapiens, replete with symbolic representations that were externalized in iconic form. We know nothing, however, about when the relevant syntactic and semantic machinery evolved, what selective pressures—if any—were responsible for its emergence, and when such internal computations were externalized in spoken or signed language. Whenever this occurred, present evidence suggests it was after our divergence with Neanderthals, and thus, a very recent event."

". . .even in the best understood cases, the genotype-phenotype gap remains large. Constructing bridge theories becomes more difficult because we must unravel regulatory networks not directly “wired” to phenotypes. Konopka et al. (2012) have begun unraveling this structure by a functional, modular analysis of the human vs. nonh
uman primate transcriptome, but much remains unknown. Further, language is not like the examples of body plan segmentation or eye formation where functional and developmental processes are well understood in numerous species, both closely and distantly related. There are simply no precise analogs or homologs of human language in other species."

"The vast majority of modeling efforts, like those above, presuppose the existence of a language phenotype equipped with compositionality and discrete infinity. This assumption is directly built into the mathematical models (Nowak and Komarova, 2001; Kirby and Hurford, 2002) or enabled by human subjects in behavioral studies, who may impose linguistic structures upon the materials presented (Kirby et al., 2008). But this presupposition regarding the language phenotype offers no insight into how it arose in the first place, nor does it illuminate the fundamental distinction between the emergence of the core biological competence and its adaptive or non-adaptive functions. Lastly, the underlying assumptions of these models, including their commitment to an adaptationist program, are often made without empirical verification and in some cases, are contrary to known facts about languages. As noted in our section How to Study the Evolution of a Trait, it is essential for proposals of adaptive function to be tested against non-adaptive hypotheses."

Frontiers | The mystery of language evolution | Language Sciences
 
Weiskrantz, Lawrence, editor
Thought Without Language
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988

"Does thought depend crucially on language, as some philosophers maintain, or can abstract reasoning and related capacities exist in the absence of language? This volume, based on a Fyssen Foundation symposium held in Versailles in April 1987, addresses this question in a new way, bringing together for the first time three different groups of experts who usually view it from different angles. From studies of the cognitive capacities of pre-linguistic human infants, of the 'silent' right cerebral hemisphere in human adults, and of animals, including birds, rodents, dogs, and primates, there emerges an impressive body of material that sheds new light on the question. Topics covered include the ability of young pre-linguistic infants to perceive causation and to make inferences concerning the structure of the perceived world, the reasoning ability of patients with severe language problems caused by brain damage to the left hemisphere, the skills that animals and infants show in combining separate items of spatial knowledge into an integrated spatial map, the capacity of chimpanzees to add unequal arithmetic fractions, the forming of perceptual categories by infants and what might be a contrasting approach by pigeons, evidence for a variety of types of cognition without conscious awareness in human patients, and what may be homologous processes in animals."

Weiskrantz (1988): Thought Without Language
 
Last edited:
This is wonderful, like Ann Sullivan's gift of language and world to Helen Keller:

"What happened is that I saw a movement. I stopped. I was talking to an empty chair, but out of my peripheral vision I saw something move. I look at Ildefonso and he had just become rigid! He actually sat up in his chair and became rigid. His hands were flat on the table and his eyes were wide. His facial expression was different from any I’d seen. It was just wide with amazement!

And then he started-it was the most emotional moment with another human being, I think, in my life so that even now, after all these years, I’m choking up [pauses]-he started pointing to everything in the room, and this is amazing to me! I’ve thought about this for years. It’s not having language that separates us from other animals, it’s because we love it! All of a sudden, this twenty-seven-year-old man-who, of course, had seen a wall and a door and a window before-started pointing to everything. He pointed to the table. He wanted me to sign table. He wanted the symbol. He wanted the name for table. And he wanted the symbol, the sign, for window.

The amazing thing is that the look on his face was as if he had never seen a window before. The window became a different thing with a symbol attached to it. [emphasis added, GD] But it’s not just a symbol. It’s a shared symbol. He can say “window” to someone else tomorrow who he hasn’t even met yet! And they will know what a window is. There’s something magical that happens between humans and symbols and the sharing of symbols.

That was his first “Aha!” He just went crazy for a few seconds, pointing to everything in the room and signing whatever I signed. Then he collapsed and started crying, and I don’t mean just a few tears. He cradled his head in his arms on the table and the table was shaking loudly from his sobbing. Of course, I don’t know what was in his head, but I’m just guessing he saw what he had missed for twenty-seven years."

Read the article here for the full context:

Life without language « Neuroanthropology
 
Extract from the continuation of that paper:

"The role of language in cognition

There’s really no way to discuss the long and complicated philosophical tradition of discussing the relation between language and cognition without being glib and superficial, but, happily, I’m pretty adept at glib and superficial, so that won’t stop us. A number of philosophers, including Michael Dummet, have offered ‘strong’ theories of language’s role in thought. Their ‘language-first’ approaches argue to varying degrees that certain kinds of thought, or even reflective thought as a whole, is only possible once a community-wide practice of communication through language occurs. We can find strong and weak variants in the work of theorists like William Calvin, Merlin Donald and Daniel Dennett.

Language-first models predict that thought is more or less limited by the absence of language, the strongest suggesting that most of thought would be disrupted, and posit a definitive break in the forms of cognition available once human had produced language. The language-first approach also generally suggests that cognitive capacities vary with one’s language ability, meaning that not all linguistic communities likely have the same cognitive capacities. One noteworthy example is work on the Pirahã, a Brazilian Native American group whose language lacks numbers according to many researchers (see Frank et al. 2008, or a popular press version at The Independent or see the collection of Pirahã-related links at Language Log).

In contrast, opposing ‘thought-first’ arguments suggest that language expresses thought rather than being a precondition for thought occurring. For example, Jerry Fodor has argued that a prior ‘language-of-thought,’ sometimes referred to as ‘mentalese,’ underlies language ability, and partially explains similarities among languages. The thought-first model, however, can develop a problem of infinite regress, as it’s unclear how the ‘language-of-thought’ itself arises except from a prior set of symbols.

In the corner of the ‘thought-first’ argument, we could site a range of empirical evidence, such as the work of psychologists Susan Hespos and Elizabeth Spelke. Hespos and Spelke (2004), for example, found that five-month-old infants born to English-speaking parents perceived object relations concepts that were not highlighted in English, and that their parents did not see as perceptually salient (a relationship of ‘tight-’ and ‘loose-fitting’ that their research had shown to be salient to Korean speakers, whose language does highlight this distinction). That is, the infants in the English-language environment seemed to develop a pre-linguistic concept that was not supported by their first language, and thus the distinction atrophied and disappeared from their perceptions (much as sounds that are not featured in one’s language become less perceptually vivid after six months of age, eventually becoming hard to perceive).

In anthropology, Edward Sapir and Benjamin Whorf are frequently credited with bringing into sharp focus the role of language in shaping perception and cognition, although they arguably offered a less deterministic account of the relationship than some language-first philosophers (see our posts, Sapir-Whorf hypothesis is right… sort of? and Sapir-Whorf hypothesis was right… about adults, for more of a discussion of the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis). Their approach suggests that language biases perception, affecting how people are capable of perceiving, making some ideas or even qualities of the phenomenal world, more or less difficult to perceive. Coupled with work like that of Hespos and Spelke, the work on language biasing perception suggests that pre-linguistic perception is actually more attuned to sensory discrimination that may later disappear if not buttressed by language; that is, the pre-linguistic conceptual world is perhaps more attuned to certain gradations, less likely to overlook intermediate or uncategorized sensations.

When we actually look at the evidence in Schaller’s account, we find that neither a ‘language-first’ nor a ‘thought-first’ model seems to capture the inconsistency of Ildefonso’s conceptual capacities. Schaller suggests that his ‘brain was kept alive with problem solving,’ figuring out how to get money, whether by begging or working, find food and shelter, and interact with people who were unable to communicate with him.

Ironically, he seemed to understand certain sorts of symbolic processes, such as performative identity. Schaller says he apparently understood, for example, ‘macho behavior’ because he ‘could see that.’ But other sorts of processes – she says things Ildefonso ‘couldn’t see’ – they remained a mystery; she offers ‘history’ and immigration patrols in the US as two examples. In fact, of course, the division is not really visible-invisible (after all, border police are quite visible when they arrest a person), nor is it symbolic-non-symbolic (macho behaviour, after all, is a symbolically rich performance). Rather, Ildefonso’s difficulties and his successful abilities suggest to me that our own category of ‘symbol’ glosses cognitive capacities that are not all identically difficult, nor are they all dependent upon either shared symbol or language. That is, our concept of ‘symbol’ may, in fact, blind us to the very divisions that Ildefonso’s disability sketches out; not all symbols are equally symbolic, we might say. The degree of arbitrariness, for example, or the hierarchical nature of some symbols — premised on other symbols — might make them particularly opaque to the language-less. . . . "
 
Last edited:
The last blue-highlighted section above ^

Ildefonso’s difficulties and his successful abilities suggest to me that our own category of ‘symbol’ glosses cognitive capacities that are not all identically difficult, nor are they all dependent upon either shared symbol or language. That is, our concept of ‘symbol’ may, in fact, blind us to the very divisions that Ildefonso’s disability sketches out; not all symbols are equally symbolic, we might say. The degree of arbitrariness, for example, or the hierarchical nature of some symbols — premised on other symbols — might make them particularly opaque to the language-less. . . .

contains food for thought on how pre-language homo sapiens as well as very young children become aware of the compresent relationship of their own consciousness, other consciousnesses, and the encompassing world. I haven't yet read Merleau-Ponty's first book, The Structure of Behavior, or what is available from his lectures on child language acquisition at the Sorbonne, but my impression is that it is there we will find real insights into 'thought before language' based in his phenomenological theory of language as 'gesture' in primordial social experience -- gesturing toward someone or something in the world as the instantiation of understanding the relationship among oneself, other persons, and the world in which they coexist. It seems reasonable to suppose that this primordial grasp of 'world'-- and of oneself and others as interacting beings within it -- is what leads to the 'theory of mind' that child psychologists have discerned in two-year-olds. This sense of the structure of 'lived reality' is also incipient, in my opinion, in animals who live among humans.

It seems to me that the above considerations would have to become involved (and many more like them) in Tonini's Integrated Information Theory of Consciousness if it is to contribute significantly to the project of understanding what consciousness is.
 
Last edited:
Green Ideas Sleeping Furiously
Howard Gardner
The New York Review of Books, March 23, 1995

The Language Instinct: How The Mind Creates Language by Steven Pinker. Morrow, 494 pp., $23.00; HarperCollins, $14.00 (paper)

Beyond Modularity: A Developmental Perspective on Cognitive Science by Annette Karmiloff-Smith Bradford/MIT Press, 234 pp., $34.95

Acts of Meaning by Jerome Bruner. Harvard University Press, 179 pp., $19.95 (cloth), $9.95 (paper)

Extract:

"In 1975, Chomsky entered into an intellectual confrontation of another sort. At a symposium at Royaumont, outside Paris, he engaged in a debate lasting several days with Jean Piaget, who was then almost eighty years old. Piaget was not a behaviorist – indeed, he had spent decades in almost solitary opposition to Skinner and his followers – and he accepted many of the same structuralist, formalist, and cognitive ideas as Chomsky did. A conciliator by nature, Piaget seemed quite prepared to have a polite discussion in which he and Chomsky would underscore their many common views and perhaps agree to disagree on a few particulars.

But Chomsky would have none of this. Chomsky debates with great ferocity and delights in not merely distinguishing himself from others but devastating their arguments; he (along with his close colleague, the philosopher Jerry Fodor) proceeded to attack Piaget's fundamental principles. Piaget, a biologist by training, rejected explanations based on native abilities or "innate ideas" in favor of a perspective which emphasized a progression of more and more complex interactions between human beings and physical objects. For example, virtually all infants eventually learn that objects continue to exist even when they are out of sight, and all schoolchildren eventually understand that the number of objects in a group is independent of the way in which these objects happen to he arranged. According to Piaget, children only come to these understandings after months of experimentation with different objects in different contexts.

To Chomskians, such talk of "interaction" and "context" is beside the point. We know what we know because of our biological heritage. In debate, Chomsky (and Fodor) insisted that human language was only possible because of linguistic structures that derive from the human genome. Where Piaget saw the child's development as a sequence of qualitatively distinct stages, Chomsky (and Fodor) argued that in explaining the child's acquisition of language, there was no need for any notion at all of development or learning. Where Piaget believed that language ability depends upon certain experiences in infancy, Chomsky (and Fodor) questioned the need to identify any particular stages on the way to a person's linguistic competence. Chomsky criticized the followers of Skinner and Piaget for their insensitivity to what was special about language. He challenged their inclination to view language acquisition as part of "general intelligence," and to assimilate language to other mental representations, such as those involved in visual imagery or the classification of objects.

Chomsky was developing the case for what Fodor called modularity. Instead of treating the mind as if it were an all-purpose computer that deals in the same way with data ranging from linguistic signals to musical tones to visual patterns, Chomsky took the view that the mind consists of a set of quite distinct computational devices. His mission was to lay bare the structure and processes of the "mental organ," or module, specifically governing language, and to demonstrate that it operated according to its own genetically programmed laws."

Gardner: Green Ideas Sleeping Furiously
 
Perception-Cognition Interface & Cross-Modal Experiences: Insights into Unified Consciousness
Topic Editors:

Aleksandra Mroczko-Wasowicz, National Yang Ming University, Taiwan
Deadline for full article submission: 30 Sep 2014

"Traditionally cognition and conscious perception as well as its different sense modalities have been examined independently, as divided and different from each other. However, recent studies elucidating the impact of perception on cognition, but also the various ways in which conscious perceptual experiences can be penetrated and modified by cognitive states such as thoughts, beliefs, moods, desires, emotions, knowledge and memories, seem to support an alternative view. Investigations of cross-modal experiences and multimodal interactions, in which input in one sense modality elicits or modulates contents in another modality, reveal that such perceptual experiences cannot be easily categorized as belonging to one of the traditional five senses. The existence of multisensory influences on perception and cross-domain integration going beyond the senses to the domains of abstract, conceptually represented entities, domains of bodily, motor and emotional states, provide challenges to standard methods individuating our epistemic abilities. This implies a need for a new methodology. A full understanding of how the mind works requires considering the complex and tight relations holding among these domains and their mutual impact. Our mental faculties should not only be studied separately. They call for a more holistic approach in order to uncover their extensive capacity for interaction producing unified conscious experiences.

The Research Topic “Perception-Cognition Interface & Cross-Modal Experiences: Insights into Unified Consciousness” is open to both theoretical and empirical contributions from different fields (e.g., philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience) in the form of original research articles, hypothesis and theory articles, reviews, opinion papers and commentaries. It aims to be an interdisciplinary reference on the links between cognition, concepts and perception as well as interactions among sense modalities to advance our understanding of the kinds of unity relation or integration processes within consciousness."

Consciousness Research | Research Topics
 
@smcder, Steve, this research topic and forthcoming publications in the Consciousness Research section at the Frontiers site will certainly interest you and might be a publishing opportunity for you as well.


Interoception, Contemplative Practice, and Health

Topic Editors:
Olga Pollatos, Institue of Psychology and Education, Health Psychology, University of Ulm, Germany
Norman Farb, Baycrest, Canada
Wolf E. Mehling, University of California San Francisco, USA
Catherine Kerr, Brown University, USA

Deadline for abstract submission: 30 Jun 2014
Deadline for full article submission: 30 Sep 2014

"There is an emergent movement of scientists and scholars working on somatic awareness and embodiment. This work cuts across studies of neurophysiology, somatic anthropology, contemplative practice, and mind-body medicine. Some of the key questions include: How is body awareness cultivated? What role does interoception play for emotion and cognition in healthy adults and children as well as in different psychopathologies? What are the neurophysiological effects of this cultivation in practices such as Yoga, mindfulness meditation, Tai Chi and other embodied contemplative practices? What categories from other traditions might be useful as we explore embodiment? Does the cultivation of body awareness within contemplative practice offer a tool for coping with suffering from conditions, such as pain, addiction, and dysregulated emotion?

This emergent field of research into somatic awareness and associated interoceptive processes, however, faces many obstacles. The principle obstacle lies in our 400-year Cartesian tradition that views sensory perception as epiphenomenal to cognition. The segregation of perception and cognition has enabled a broad program of cognitive science research, but may have also prevented researchers from developing paradigms for understanding how interoceptive awareness of sensations from inside the body influences cognition. The cognitive representation of interoceptive signals may play an active role in facilitating therapeutic transformation, e.g. by altering context in which cognitive appraisals of well-being occur. This topic has ramifications into disparate research fields: What is the role of interoceptive awareness in conscious presence? How do we distinguish between adaptive and maladaptive somatic awareness? How do we best measure somatic awareness? What are the consequences of dysregulated somatic/interoceptive awareness on cognition, emotion, and behavior? The complexity of these questions calls for the creative integration of perspectives and findings from related but often disparate research areas including clinical research, neuroscience, cognitive psychology, anthropology, religious/contemplative studies and philosophy.

We would like to invite the scientific community to join in the discussion of these questions. Frontiers in Psychology offers an online dialogue to intensify collaborations and drive the next research in our field. We welcome new empirical findings, theoretical proposals as well as thorough scientific reviews, and specific topics can include but are not limited to:
• Neurological processes underlying the differentiation between contrasting modes of interoceptive awareness: hypervigilant or mindful.
• Embodied cognition and contemplative practices
• Interoceptive phenomenology across Eastern and Western cultural perspectives (prāna)
• Behavioral measures for modes of interoceptive awareness beyond interoceptive accuracy
• Measurable effects of contemplative practices on interoceptive awareness and accuracy
• Determination when interventions are appropriate that enhance interoceptive awareness or use interoceptive exposure in psychopathological conditions.
• Changes in interoceptive awareness and/or accuracy mediating health benefits from contemplative practices
• Role of interoceptive processes in emotion and cognition
• Interoceptive awareness in children
• Interoceptive awareness as an element of compassion
• Theoretical reviews for mechanisms underlying dysfunctional interoception.
• Evaluation of interoceptive exposure or awareness training as therapeutic applications for clinical populations"

Consciousness Research | Research Topics
 
Constance, thanks for sharing all these wonderful resources. A lifetime's worth of reading material.

I do think human consciousness is distinct from other consciousnesses as it is generated by the human organism. So it's possible that certain human mental capabilities - such as language - are contingent on the physical human organism.

However, I think that human-capacity-like consciousness can theoretically be produced by non-human organisms or systems. Such non-human consciousnesses will be as varied from human consciousnesses as the physical organisms or systems that produce them. It's possible that there are systems made of pure energy that are capable of generating consciousness. It's hard to fathom how alien such a consciousness would be from our own.

I do think trying to understand human consciousness via evolution and specifically adaptation can be problematic. While life on earth certainly has undergone evolution, the mechanisms of this processes are not completely understood or established. This is why I can't fault neuroscientists for using terms like machine and computation, etc. The human organism/brain might be a machine that was/is designed by something or someone.
 
Constance, thanks for sharing all these wonderful resources. A lifetime's worth of reading material.

Glad you find the sources useful. The open source Frontiers site is an excellent resource for new thinking in many disciplines, and the topics in the consciousness research section are all relevant to this thread. (I haven't linked them all.)
 
I am going to try to throw a general reset into this forum--for the most part since I am a "lurker" who waits till something really makes me shift views. I find it useful to inform others when my views have shifted...not sure why, which you might think such an excuse is grounds to dismissing my remarks at the first realization of this fact (if you could determine the exact time you realize or realized this, then you may pass...)

So letting the unsuccessful dry jokes pass without much comment (wishful thinking), I will allow myself the prerogative (what does this mean?) of pretending the entire thread (as amazing and interesting as it is) has passed into and through my "mind" -- whatever that may be.


Take the fundamental quantities of physics (I am trying to get to the fundamental ontic root here...so this may sound strange to both philosophers and scientists/mathematicians

Mass: a quantity which denotes the properties of acceleration that are related to a force (another undefined quantity)
Force: a quantity which denotes the properties of resistance to change within a particular acceleration or mass
Acceleration: A spatiotemporal property relating and resistance to change with respect to force and mass
Space: relational categories of our visual cortex -- or best left undefined (try to define it)
Time: relational categories of deltas with respect to the physical properties other than time

OK if this all sounded strange, it is because I am trying to show the inter-dependencies of these concepts...and to show the artificiality with respect to your cognition...

Why does this seem artificial? Because they are quantities that are created to comprehend the world, but they are not the objects themselves...they are part of a tunnel (borrowed from Metzinger) of reality your mind has created that makes "sense" and can be manipulated in thought...the point is not to understand the world, but to understand how to envision the future of the world or the way in which you can guarantee your continued presence in the world (Dennett).

[edit: clarification, the sufficient survival "understanding" is must less than that total world relations understanding that is fiction (i.e. knowing everything and the relations of everything to everything)...this has caused a stack overflow in our minds, because we imagine that there is no minimally sufficient "understanding" with respect to continued existence...we imagine that such an understanding must be a potential "state" even though the gene machine has already hard wired what is optimal for billions of our own predecessors...think about the astronomical quantity of trial and error of all the generations of beings prior to yourself, then ask if any supercomputer should have total "all hands of deck" awareness of such a decision net....is it necessary?]

And "continued presence" should sound like BS to you...if it does, then high-five...because I myself ask the same question, "why is presence so important, nothingness is an easier accomplishment." However you can turn the tables on this proposition by showing that nothingness (absolute non-being) is the necessary ground of all perception and cognition. This I believe I have proved here (while stupidly trying to prove something else):

Grounds for Awareness and Consciousness | Gather

Without non-being, there is no basis for which a "being" can throw itself into the foreground of processing either my a mindless machine or a thinking machine (hint: this is why there is no difference). A mind is something which is denoted by the entity itself to itself--without this relation of thing to itself there is no mind (but relations and change of things to themselves are inevitable, therefore mindlessness is the absolute foundation of mind...understand?)

Before you go west, you have to have east...before you see something, you have to not see what's around ...before you are conscious, you must be asleep...to not be surprised by anything is to never be aware of anything (this is very important and easy to understand once you try to imagine what consciousness or awareness is like to an omniscient being)

Hope this helps.

-Z
 
Last edited:
MA, I'm trying to parse out your post, but with admittedly limited success.

"God split himself into a myriad parts that he might have friends. This may not be true, but it sounds good, and is no sillier than any other theology." [Lazarus Long, _Time Enough for Love_ by Robert Heinlein]

Does this quote bear upon your argument by virtue of the traditional notion that nothing may be defined except by virtue of contrast ?
 
For some reason the following seems relevant......;)

You Will Never Trust Your Brain Again After These Insane Optical Illusions!

Text: Our brains have developed incredible tactics and coping mechanisms to help us make sense of the complex world around us. But some parts of our highly adaptive minds aren't perfect and can be exposed through carefully crafted illusions.

In this list, you have the luxury of knowing the images and gifs are actually illusions. But can you imagine how many ways your brain is deceiving you every day without your knowledge? In fact, its likely that everything you've ever experienced is heavily distorted so you can process and understand what you perceive.


LINK: You Will Never Trust Your Brain Again After These Insane Optical Illusions!
 
Last edited:
Status
Not open for further replies.
Back
Top